The name is absent



intuition that two people incurring equal disutility deserve equal rewards” (Kranich
1994, p. 178).
11

Definition 2 A policy is called affirmative action (AA) if:

ci(ei) = cj (ej) pi (e) = pj (e) for all i = j.

For the class of contest games as defined by the CSF in eq. (2) the following relation
with respect to the policy weights (
α1AA, . . . , αnAA) satisfies the definition of affirmative

action:


αAA   αjAA

(4)


~τr= =   ■ for all i = j.

βr βr            j

This relation is derived by using the following transformation of variables: zi = ci (ei )
for all
i N. As ci (ei ) is linear it can be inverted: ei = zi i . For the so transformed
model the condition in Definition 2 then states that if
zi = zjthen pi(z∕β) = Pj (z∕β),
where z∕β = (z1∕β1,... zn∕βn) denotes the vector of transformed individual effort.
Solving
pi (z∕β) = pj (z∕β) for zi = zj implies that: αiAA(zi ∕βi )r = αjAA(zi ∕βj)r which
has to hold for all values
zi = zj . This condition is satisfied if the above mentioned
relation holds. The following normalization simplifies the subsequent analysis. As the
CSF is homogeneous of degree zero, there is no loss in generality if the weights are
normalized such that:

αAA = βr for all i N.                            (5)

The policy AA therefore generates a bias12 of the contest success function in favor of
discriminated contestants in such a way that both contestants have the same probabil-
ity of winning the contest whenever they face the same disutility of effort. Note that
this definition requires that the affirmative action bias is implemented multiplicatively
through
αiAA which increases the marginal efficiency of exerted effort for contestant i
and therefore changes the incentives for effort distribution. This type of affirmative

11This quotation from Kranich (1994) justifies a related ‘equal-division-for-equal-work’ principle in his
model. The difference to the model presented here is that ‘equal work’ should be interpreted here
as equal disutility of effort as this is the relevant normative standard of comparison if contestants
are not responsible for the differences in marginal costs.

12In Clark and Riis (1998) it is argued that the anonymity axiom of Skaperdas (1996) should be re-
laxed because “in many situations, however, contestants are treated differently (due to affirmative
action programs for instance)” (Clark and Riis 1998, p. 201). The resulting CSF is asymmetric
as in eq. (2) but without any further specification of this asymmetry. Definition 2 can therefore
also be interpreted as a substitute of the anonymity axiom that entails now a specific normative
restriction with respect to the asymmetry of the CSF.



More intriguing information

1. Macro-regional evaluation of the Structural Funds using the HERMIN modelling framework
2. Spatial patterns in intermunicipal Danish commuting
3. Solidaristic Wage Bargaining
4. Qualification-Mismatch and Long-Term Unemployment in a Growth-Matching Model
5. Are Japanese bureaucrats politically stronger than farmers?: The political economy of Japan's rice set-aside program
6. Non-farm businesses local economic integration level: the case of six Portuguese small and medium-sized Markettowns• - a sector approach
7. The name is absent
8. Large-N and Large-T Properties of Panel Data Estimators and the Hausman Test
9. The name is absent
10. Qualifying Recital: Lisa Carol Hardaway, flute