figure 1. Although total reductions might be increased by a unilateral move, it
does not seem to be a good idea for country i to engage in unilateral actions, if
its aim of setting a good example will be strategically exploited by other coun-
tries. No rational country will ever find it worthwhile to undertake unilateral
actions under this model.
One shortcoming with Hoel’s approach is that h remains unexplained. It does
not seem to be rational for a country to engage in unilateral actions when it
knows the above relationship. This is why h cannot be a choice variable in
Hoel’s model. The interesting question remains: Can unilateral actions be ra-
tional (i.e. result from optimising behaviour) if Hoel’s (1991) reaction function
approach is used without conditioning unilateral actions on the presence of non-
choice variables?
We turn now to an examination of the way the costs influence the Nash-
equilibrium. Let θi be a shifting parameter in the cost function of country i, such
that:
∂C
(2)
(3)
C1 (qi,θi ) > Ci(qi,θi ) for θi > θi for all qi ∈ Q1 and ɪ > 0
∂θ1
In appendix 1, it is shown that
∂q1- < 0 and ∂q2- > 0, ∀i,j ∈ I
∂θ1 ∂θ1
The intuition behind (3) is that increased costs in country 1 lead to less reduc-
tions by country 1, which increases the marginal benefit to country 2 (as long as
country 2 does not change its emission). Hence, country 2 will respond by in-
creasing its reduction efforts.
13
More intriguing information
1. Nonparametric cointegration analysis2. THE ECONOMICS OF COMPETITION IN HEALTH INSURANCE- THE IRISH CASE STUDY.
3. The Evolution
4. Testing for One-Factor Models versus Stochastic Volatility Models
5. The name is absent
6. The name is absent
7. Existentialism: a Philosophy of Hope or Despair?
8. EMU's Decentralized System of Fiscal Policy
9. The name is absent
10. Educational Inequalities Among School Leavers in Ireland 1979-1994