Feasible choice rules To highlight the fact that in the above definition the
English auction is conditioned on the prior p, denote it by φE [p]. Now the function
φE : ∆(Θ) → Φ can be taken as the the English auction -choice rule. Construct a
correspondence CφE ⊂ VIC such that
Cφ [p] = ©Ф ∈ VIC[p] : Ф is not ex post dominated by φE[p0], for any p' ∈ ∆(Θ)} .
Note that the English auction -choice rule is idempotent: φE [p(x, φE [p])] =
1x , for all x ∈ φE [p](supp(p)), for all p. That is, after running the English auction,
a new English auction does not change the outcome. This implies that the English
auction φE [p] is not ex post dominated by φE[p(x, φE [p])]. Hence it follows that
φE [p] ∈ CφE [p] for all p. More compactly:
Lemma 3 φE [∙] is consistent.
If φE [p] also maximizes v in CφE [p] for all p, then φE satisfies the one-deviation
property. We now show that this necessarily holds: any mechanism in CφE [p] is
outcome equivalent - and hence payoff equivalent - with the English auction φE [p].
Lemma 4 φ ∈ CφE [p] only if φ is outcome equivalent to φE [p], for all p.
Proof. Relegated to Appendix A. ■
That is, given p, the only veto-incentive compatible mechanisms that are not ex
post dominated by any φE [p0] are the mechanism φE [p] itself and its versions that
may additionally reveal some non-relevant information concerning the winner’s
type. Thus φE has a "fixed point" property.
We next demonstrate that any stationary σ that is consistent and meets
the one-deviation property induces Cσ that contains φE , specified for some tie-
breaking rule w. Heuristically, if φ ex post dominates φE [p], then φ must change
φE [p]’s allocation. Since any outcome x of φE [p] reveals the winner and his least
possible valuation given the other buyers’ valuations, φ must threaten the win-
ner to sell the good to the buyer with the second highest valuation to force the
winner to pay a higher price. However, the threat is not credible since when the
winner declines the offer, the seller sells, by stationarity, to the winner with his
least possible valuation.
Lemma 5 Let a stationary choice rule σ be consistent and satisfy the one-deviation
property. Then there is a tie-breaking rule w such that φE [p] ∈ Cσ [p], for all p.
Proof. Construct w as follows: For any θ ∈ Θ, denote by 1θ the degenerate
prior such that supp(1θ) = {θ}. Then there is an outcome xθ such that σ[1θ] = 1xθ .
Let w(θ)=i if xθ allocates the good to i. By Lemma 2, such w(θ) satisfies (5).
Use this w to construct φE .
Suppose, to the contrary of the claim, that there is p such that φE [p] 6∈ Cσ [p].
Then φE[p] is ex post dominated by σ[p(x, φE [p])] for some x ∈ φE[p](supp(p)).
Denote σ[p(x, φE [p])] = g ◦ h.
12
More intriguing information
1. The name is absent2. On the job rotation problem
3. A Note on Productivity Change in European Co-operative Banks: The Luenberger Indicator Approach
4. The name is absent
5. Monetary Discretion, Pricing Complementarity and Dynamic Multiple Equilibria
6. INTERACTION EFFECTS OF PROMOTION, RESEARCH, AND PRICE SUPPORT PROGRAMS FOR U.S. COTTON
7. Campanile Orchestra
8. Language discrimination by human newborns and by cotton-top tamarin monkeys
9. Restricted Export Flexibility and Risk Management with Options and Futures
10. Solidaristic Wage Bargaining