Auction Design without Commitment



non-cooperative bargaining literature, and verified in the so called "gap" case
θ(p) 0 e.g. by Fudenberg et al. (1985) and Gul et al. (1986).

The next proposition shows that the result can be derived also in our set up,
without going into the details of the bargaining process. Thus consistency and the
one-deviation property do capture the key aspects of sequential rationality.

Remark 1 (Gap-case) Let n =1. Let σ be a consistent choice function meeting
the
one-deviation restriction. Then σ[p] = 1(ι,θ(p)), for all P such that θ(p) > 0.

That is, any σ [p] sells the good to the buyer with the price equal to his min-
imal possible valuation. To see this, note that by Lemma 1,
σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s) ,
for all s h(supp(p)). By Lemma 2, g(s) maximizes v in the class of constant,
individually rational mechanisms under
p(s,h). Since θ(p(s,h)) 0 we have
g(s) = (1(p(s, h))). But by imitating θ = θ(p) 0, any θ0 supp(p) can guaran-
tee to be able to buy the good with price
θ(p). Hence by incentive compatibility,
g(h(θ)) = (1(p)), for all θ supp(p).

However, it is also well known that in the "no gap" -case, θ(p) = 0, other more
complex equilibria can be constructed (see e.g. Ausubel and Deneckere, 1989).
To avoid them, the literature often focusses on simple "stationary" equilibria (see
e.g. Ausubel et al., 2001).

The problem with multiplicity of complex solutions applies also in our case
when
θ(p) = 0. It can be shown that for any λ Θ there is a choice rule σλ that
is con
sistent and meets the one-deviation property, and sells to types θ λ and
never to types
θ<λof the buyer given the prior p (see Appendix B for precise
exposition). However, all constructed
σλ are complex, and require the seller to
condition
σλ on seemingly superficial information. To remove these complexities,
our final restriction imposes a degree of simplicity on choice rules. It demands
that the implemented outcome is not conditioned on information that does not
provide more profitable transaction opportunities.

Definition 4 (Stationarity) A choice rule σ is stationary if σ[p]=1x[p0]=
1x0 , v(x) ≥ v (x0), and supp(p0) supp(p) imply x = x0 .

That is, signals that do not allow the seller to implement a more profitable
choice do not affect the seller’s choice. For example, the choice rule
σλ above fails
stationarity.16 The next section characterizes the inducable stationary choice rules
in the general
n ≥ 1 case.

4 Results

The English auction φE The tie-breaking rule w always selects one of the
players with the highest valuation:

w(θ) arg max θj , for all θ Θ.                     (5)

jN∪{0} j

16For an analogous restriction, see Ausubel and Deneckere (1992).

10



More intriguing information

1. Determinants of U.S. Textile and Apparel Import Trade
2. The name is absent
3. The name is absent
4. The name is absent
5. Großhandel: Steigende Umsätze und schwungvolle Investitionsdynamik
6. Making International Human Rights Protection More Effective: A Rational-Choice Approach to the Effectiveness of Ius Standi Provisions
7. The name is absent
8. Subduing High Inflation in Romania. How to Better Monetary and Exchange Rate Mechanisms?
9. The name is absent
10. The name is absent
11. Mergers and the changing landscape of commercial banking (Part II)
12. The name is absent
13. The geography of collaborative knowledge production: entropy techniques and results for the European Union
14. Influence of Mucilage Viscosity On The Globule Structure And Stability Of Certain Starch Emulsions
15. Effects of a Sport Education Intervention on Students’ Motivational Responses in Physical Education
16. If our brains were simple, we would be too simple to understand them.
17. The name is absent
18. Crime as a Social Cost of Poverty and Inequality: A Review Focusing on Developing Countries
19. Structural Conservation Practices in U.S. Corn Production: Evidence on Environmental Stewardship by Program Participants and Non-Participants
20. SLA RESEARCH ON SELF-DIRECTION: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ISSUES