Auction Design without Commitment



The second condition implies optimality. Given σ and p, the seller should
choose a mechanism that maximizes her payoff in the set C
σ [p].

Definition 3 (One-Deviation Property) Choice rule σ satisfies the one-deviation
property if v
(σ[p],p) v(φ, p), for all φ Cσ [p], for all p.

Under the hypothesis that σ can be committed to in the future, the seller
does not want to change σ under any current prior p. Without the one-deviation
property σ could not be convincingly committed to. One-deviation property is in
line with standard equilibrium reasoning. Indeed it is often drawn as a consequence
of it.

Now we state two straightforward but important implications of consistency
and the one-deviation property. First, the seller always implements the outcome
of a mechanism that she can commit to.

Lemma 1 Let σ be consistent and satisfy the one-deviation property. Then gh
Cσ [p] implies that σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s) , for all s h(supp(p)).

Proof. Take any s h(supp(p)). By consistency, gh is not ex post domi-
nated by
σ[p(s, h)] under p. By the definition of ex post dominance, 1g(s) is not
ex post dominated by
σ[p(s, h)]. Hence either v(g(s)) > v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) or
v(g(s)) = v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) and σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s) . By the one-deviation prop-
erty,
v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) v(g(s)). Hence it must be the case that σ[p(s, h)] =
1g(s). и

In particular, the choice rule σ is idempotent in the following sense: if σ[p] =
gh, then σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s), for all s h(supp(p)). That is, running σ twice in a
row rather than once will not affect the outcome.

Second, if the seller can commit to implementing an outcome, then that out-
come must maximize her payoff in the class of individually rational outcomes.

Lemma 2 Let σ satisfy the one-deviation property. Then σ[p] = 1x implies that
v(x) v(y), for all 1y VIC[p].

Proof. Let σ[p] = 1x, v(x) < v(y), and 1y VIC[p]. Since σ[p] VIC[p],
and since neither 1x nor 1y are ex post dominated by 1x, we have 1x, 1y Cσ [p].
But this violates the one-deviation property. ■

We now check that our solution is consistent with the standard bargaining
theory.

The Coase conjecture The Coase conjecture, which pertains to our n =1
case, argues that when the seller is unable to commit not to sell the good, the
buyer is able to extract all the surplus. That is, the outcome of the one-sided
bargaining game is to sell the good with price θ
(p), the minimal possible valuation
θ in the support of p. The Coase conjecture has been extensively studied in the



More intriguing information

1. Demand Potential for Goat Meat in Southern States: Empirical Evidence from a Multi-State Goat Meat Consumer Survey
2. THE RISE OF RURAL-TO-RURAL LABOR MARKETS IN CHINA
3. Tourism in Rural Areas and Regional Development Planning
4. Incorporating global skills within UK higher education of engineers
5. Segmentación en la era de la globalización: ¿Cómo encontrar un segmento nuevo de mercado?
6. The Effects of Reforming the Chinese Dual-Track Price System
7. QUEST II. A Multi-Country Business Cycle and Growth Model
8. MULTIMODAL SEMIOTICS OF SPIRITUAL EXPERIENCES: REPRESENTING BELIEFS, METAPHORS, AND ACTIONS
9. Multi-Agent System Interaction in Integrated SCM
10. Regional Intergration and Migration: An Economic Geography Model with Hetergenous Labour Force
11. The problem of anglophone squint
12. The name is absent
13. The name is absent
14. The Shepherd Sinfonia
15. The name is absent
16. Short report "About a rare cause of primary hyperparathyroidism"
17. A Rare Presentation of Crohn's Disease
18. IMPLICATIONS OF CHANGING AID PROGRAMS TO U.S. AGRICULTURE
19. The Impact of Hosting a Major Sport Event on the South African Economy
20. Skill and work experience in the European knowledge economy