Auction Design without Commitment



The second condition implies optimality. Given σ and p, the seller should
choose a mechanism that maximizes her payoff in the set C
σ [p].

Definition 3 (One-Deviation Property) Choice rule σ satisfies the one-deviation
property if v
(σ[p],p) v(φ, p), for all φ Cσ [p], for all p.

Under the hypothesis that σ can be committed to in the future, the seller
does not want to change σ under any current prior p. Without the one-deviation
property σ could not be convincingly committed to. One-deviation property is in
line with standard equilibrium reasoning. Indeed it is often drawn as a consequence
of it.

Now we state two straightforward but important implications of consistency
and the one-deviation property. First, the seller always implements the outcome
of a mechanism that she can commit to.

Lemma 1 Let σ be consistent and satisfy the one-deviation property. Then gh
Cσ [p] implies that σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s) , for all s h(supp(p)).

Proof. Take any s h(supp(p)). By consistency, gh is not ex post domi-
nated by
σ[p(s, h)] under p. By the definition of ex post dominance, 1g(s) is not
ex post dominated by
σ[p(s, h)]. Hence either v(g(s)) > v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) or
v(g(s)) = v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) and σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s) . By the one-deviation prop-
erty,
v(σ[p(s, h)], p(s, h)) v(g(s)). Hence it must be the case that σ[p(s, h)] =
1g(s). и

In particular, the choice rule σ is idempotent in the following sense: if σ[p] =
gh, then σ[p(s, h)] = 1g(s), for all s h(supp(p)). That is, running σ twice in a
row rather than once will not affect the outcome.

Second, if the seller can commit to implementing an outcome, then that out-
come must maximize her payoff in the class of individually rational outcomes.

Lemma 2 Let σ satisfy the one-deviation property. Then σ[p] = 1x implies that
v(x) v(y), for all 1y VIC[p].

Proof. Let σ[p] = 1x, v(x) < v(y), and 1y VIC[p]. Since σ[p] VIC[p],
and since neither 1x nor 1y are ex post dominated by 1x, we have 1x, 1y Cσ [p].
But this violates the one-deviation property. ■

We now check that our solution is consistent with the standard bargaining
theory.

The Coase conjecture The Coase conjecture, which pertains to our n =1
case, argues that when the seller is unable to commit not to sell the good, the
buyer is able to extract all the surplus. That is, the outcome of the one-sided
bargaining game is to sell the good with price θ
(p), the minimal possible valuation
θ in the support of p. The Coase conjecture has been extensively studied in the



More intriguing information

1. The name is absent
2. Are combination forecasts of S&P 500 volatility statistically superior?
3. Improving the Impact of Market Reform on Agricultural Productivity in Africa: How Institutional Design Makes a Difference
4. The name is absent
5. Analyse des verbraucherorientierten Qualitätsurteils mittels assoziativer Verfahren am Beispiel von Schweinefleisch und Kartoffeln
6. The name is absent
7. El Mercosur y la integración económica global
8. Public-private sector pay differentials in a devolved Scotland
9. The name is absent
10. DETERMINANTS OF FOOD AWAY FROM HOME AMONG AFRICAN-AMERICANS