She wants to maximize her expected payoff subject to the constraint of not re-
designing the mechanism after observing the signal s from the information process-
ing device h. That is, of replacing the outcome g(s) with another mechanism in
Φ that generates her a higher expected payoff than g(s). Our task is to identify
conditions under which she will not do that.
Let the seller’s (pure) mechanism design strategy be captured by a choice rule
σ that specifies, for each prior belief p, a mechanism that the seller can commit
to under these beliefs:
σ : ∆(Θ) → Φ such that σ[p] ∈ VIC[p], for all p. (3)
Then σ [p] represents the mechanism that the seller implements under p. Rule σ
represent in reduced form the dynamic mechanism selection strategy of the seller.
We now identify properties that the choice rule σ should satisfy. We argue
that sequential rationality of the seller, and the buyers’ knowledge of this, asks σ
to reflect internal consistency and maximization. To present these conditions, we
develop some concepts. We say that a mechanism g ◦ h ∈ Φ is (weakly) ex post
dominated by a mechanism φ ∈ Φ if there is a signal s ∈ h(supp(p)) such that
v(φ, p(s, h)) ≥ v(g(s)) and φ 6= 1g(s) under p(s, h).
That is, the seller weakly prefers φ over the recommended outcome g(s), given the
ex post information due to signal s. In such case, the original mechanism g ◦ h
may be subject to redesign. It is easy to see that in a typical scenario, there is no
veto-incentive compatible mechanism that is not ex post dominated.15 Thus the
seller is typically (weakly) tempted to redesign the mechanism.
Under prior p, denote by Cσ [p] the set of mechanisms that are not subject to
redesign under the hypothesis that σ is followed ex post:
Cσ [p]={g ◦ h ∈ VIC[p]:g ◦ h is not ex post dominated by σ[p(s, h)], for any s ∈ h(supp(p))} .
(4)
Hence, by the revelation principle, and under the hypothesis that the seller can
commit to the choice rule σ :
• a mechanism φ is truthfully playable if φ ∈ Cσ [p], since then it will not be
redesigned ex post, and
• a mechanism φ is not truthfully playable if φ 6∈ Cσ [p], since then it will be
redesigned ex post.
We now specify formally conditions that sequential rationality imposes on the
choice rule σ . The first condition requires consistency in the sense that employing
σ ex ante should not contradict σ being employed ex post.
Definition 2 (Consistency) Choice rule σ is consistent if σ[p] ∈ Cσ [p], for all
p.
15If 0 ∈supp(pi) for all i, then a veto-incentive compatible mechanism is not ex post dominated
only if extracts all surplus from the buyers. But full surplus extraction a la Cremes and McLean
(1984) is not possible under veto-incentive compatibility.
More intriguing information
1. The name is absent2. ARE VOLATILITY EXPECTATIONS CHARACTERIZED BY REGIME SHIFTS? EVIDENCE FROM IMPLIED VOLATILITY INDICES
3. Une nouvelle vision de l'économie (The knowledge society: a new approach of the economy)
4. Geography, Health, and Demo-Economic Development
5. Nurses' retention and hospital characteristics in New South Wales, CHERE Discussion Paper No 52
6. THE WELFARE EFFECTS OF CONSUMING A CANCER PREVENTION DIET
7. Fortschritte bei der Exportorientierung von Dienstleistungsunternehmen
8. The name is absent
9. Howard Gardner : the myth of Multiple Intelligences
10. Name Strategy: Its Existence and Implications