Auction Design without Commitment



She wants to maximize her expected payoff subject to the constraint of not re-
designing the mechanism after observing the signal
s from the information process-
ing device
h. That is, of replacing the outcome g(s) with another mechanism in
Φ that generates her a higher expected payoff than g(s). Our task is to identify
conditions under which she will not do that.

Let the seller’s (pure) mechanism design strategy be captured by a choice rule
σ
that specifies, for each prior belief p, a mechanism that the seller can commit
to under these beliefs:

σ : ∆(Θ) → Φ such that σ[p] VIC[p], for all p.           (3)

Then σ [p] represents the mechanism that the seller implements under p. Rule σ
represent in reduced form the dynamic mechanism selection strategy of the seller.

We now identify properties that the choice rule σ should satisfy. We argue
that sequential rationality of the seller, and the buyers’ knowledge of this, asks
σ
to reflect internal consistency and maximization. To present these conditions, we
develop some concepts. We say that a mechanism
g ◦ h Φ is (weakly) ex post
dominated
by a mechanism φ Φ if there is a signal s h(supp(p)) such that

v(φ, p(s, h)) ≥ v(g(s)) and φ 6= 1g(s) under p(s, h).

That is, the seller weakly prefers φ over the recommended outcome g(s), given the
ex post information due to signal
s. In such case, the original mechanism g ◦ h
may be subject to redesign. It is easy to see that in a typical scenario, there is no
veto-incentive compatible mechanism that is not ex post dominated.15 Thus the
seller is typically (weakly) tempted to redesign the mechanism.

Under prior p, denote by Cσ [p] the set of mechanisms that are not subject to
redesign under the hypothesis that
σ is followed ex post:

Cσ [p]={g ◦ h VIC[p]:g ◦ h is not ex post dominated by σ[p(s, h)], for any s h(supp(p))} .
(4)

Hence, by the revelation principle, and under the hypothesis that the seller can
commit to the choice rule
σ :

a mechanism φ is truthfully playable if φ Cσ [p], since then it will not be
redesigned ex post, and

a mechanism φ is not truthfully playable if φ 6 Cσ [p], since then it will be
redesigned ex post.

We now specify formally conditions that sequential rationality imposes on the
choice rule
σ . The first condition requires consistency in the sense that employing
σ ex ante should not contradict σ being employed ex post.

Definition 2 (Consistency) Choice rule σ is consistent if σ[p] Cσ [p], for all
p.

15If 0 supp(pi) for all i, then a veto-incentive compatible mechanism is not ex post dominated
only if extracts all surplus from the buyers. But full surplus extraction a la Cremes and McLean
(1984) is not possible under veto-incentive compatibility.



More intriguing information

1. The name is absent
2. Knowledge, Innovation and Agglomeration - regionalized multiple indicators and evidence from Brazil
3. Modeling industrial location decisions in U.S. counties
4. THE MEXICAN HOG INDUSTRY: MOVING BEYOND 2003
5. Disentangling the Sources of Pro-social Behavior in the Workplace: A Field Experiment
6. Three Policies to Improve Productivity Growth in Canada
7. fMRI Investigation of Cortical and Subcortical Networks in the Learning of Abstract and Effector-Specific Representations of Motor Sequences
8. The Prohibition of the Proposed Springer-ProSiebenSat.1-Merger: How much Economics in German Merger Control?
9. The name is absent
10. The name is absent