Constrained School Choice



the empty list. Let Q := (Qi, Q-i). By a result of Gale and Sotomayor (1985b, Theorem
2) extended to the college admissions model (Roth and Sotomayor, 1990, Theorem 5.34),
for each
j I\i, either γ(Q)(j) = γ(Q)(j) or γ(Q^)(j)QjY(Q)(j). Hence, the set of
schools to which each
j ∈ I\i proposes in DA(Q) is a subset of the schools to which
he proposes in
DA(Q). Since moreover Qi is the empty list, each school receives in
DA(Q) only a subset of the proposals of DA(Q). For school s this immediately implies
that
∣γ(dQ)(s)∣ ≤ ∣γ(Q)(s)∣ < qs. So, if we take Qi = s then γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) = s. Since
sPiγ(Q)(i), Qi is a profitable deviation for i at Q in Γγ(P, k). So, Q ∈ Eγ(P, k), a
contradiction. Hence,
γ(Q) ∈ NW(P).                                            

Proof of Theorem 5.3 It suffices to prove the theorem for k = k+ 1. Let Q ∈ Eγ(P, k)
and suppose that
Q ∈ Eγ(P, k +1). Then, there is a student i and a strategy Qi ∈ Q(k + 1)
with
γ(Qi,Q-i)Piγ(Qi,Q-i). By Lemma A.2, γ(Q) ∈ IR(P). Hence, γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) ∈ S.
Note also that
Qi must be a list containing exactly k + 1 schools, for otherwise it would
also be a profitable deviation in Γ
γ(P, k), contradicting Q ∈ Eγ(P, k).

Let s be the last school listed in Q'i. We claim that γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) = s. Suppose
Y(Qi,Q-i)(i) = s. Consider the truncation of Qi after γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) and denote this list
by
Qi. In other words, Qiis the list obtained from Qi by making all schools listed after
Y (Qi, Q-i)(i) unacceptable. By assumption, Qi∈ Q(k). It follows from the DA algorithm
that
Y(Qi, Q-i) = Y(Qi, Q-i). Hence, Qi is a profitable deviation for i at Q in Γγ(P, k),
a contradiction. So,
Y(Qi, Q-i)(i) = s.

Let Qi := s. Note Qi Q(k). By Lemma A.1, γ((Qi,Q-i)(i') = s. Hence, Qi is a
profitable deviation for
i at Q in Γγ(P, k), a contradiction. Hence, Q ∈ Eγ(P, k + 1).

We need the following three lemmas to prove Theorem 6.5.

Lemma A.3 Let f be an Ergin-cyclic priority structure. Let 2 ≤ k ≤ m. Then, there
is a school choice problem
P with an unstable equilibrium outcome in the game Γγ (P, k),
i.e., for some
Q ∈ Eγ(P,k), Y(Q) ∈ S(P).

Proof Since f is Ergin-cyclic, we may assume, without loss of generality, that

(a) fs1(i1) < fs1 (i2) < fs1(i3) and fs2(i3) < fs2(i1),

(b) fs1 (ij) < fs1 (i2) for each j ∈ I1 := {4, . . . , qs1 + 2}, and

(c) fs2 (ij) < fs2 (i1) for each j ∈ I2 := {qs1 + 3, . . . , qs1 + qs2 + 1}.

Consider students’ preferences P defined by Pi1 := s2, s1 , Pi2 := s1 , Pi3 := s1, s2,

Pij := si for j ∈ Iι, Pij := s2 for j ∈ I2, and Pij := 0 for all j ∈ {q31 + qβ2 + 2,..., n}.

29



More intriguing information

1. The name is absent
2. Synthesis and biological activity of α-galactosyl ceramide KRN7000 and galactosyl (α1→2) galactosyl ceramide
3. The name is absent
4. CREDIT SCORING, LOAN PRICING, AND FARM BUSINESS PERFORMANCE
5. The name is absent
6. The name is absent
7. The name is absent
8. The name is absent
9. Critical Race Theory and Education: Racism and antiracism in educational theory and praxis David Gillborn*
10. TOWARDS THE ZERO ACCIDENT GOAL: ASSISTING THE FIRST OFFICER MONITOR AND CHALLENGE CAPTAIN ERRORS