We distinguish among three cases for the priority ordering fs2 of school s2 with respect
to students i1, i2, and i3: (i) fs2 (i2) < fs2 (i3) < fs2 (i1), (ii) fs2 (i3) < fs2 (i2) < fs2 (i1),
and (iii) fs2 (i3) < fs2 (i1) < fs2 (i2). One easily verifies that in each of the cases (i), (ii),
and (iii), the unique stable matching for P is μ* = γ(P) with μ*(i1) = s1, μ*(i3) = s2,
and μ*(i2) = i2.
Consider Q ∈ Q(k)I defined by Qi2 := 0 and Qi := Pi for all i ∈ I∖i2. One easily
verifies that in each of the cases (i), (ii), and (iii), γ(Q)(i1) = s2 and γ(Q)(i3) = s1. So,
γ (Q) = μ*, and hence γ(Q) ∈ S (P ). Finally, one easily verifies that Q ∈ Eγ (P, k). ■
A mechanism is non bossy if no student can maintain his allotment and cause a change
in the other students’ allotments by reporting different preferences.
Definition A.4 Non Bossy Mechanism (Satterthwaite and Sonnenschein, 1981)
A mechanism φ is non bossy if for all i ∈ I, Qi, Qi ∈ Q, and Q-i ∈ QI\i, φ(Q'i, Q-i)(i) =
φ(Qi,Q-i)(i) implies φ(Q'i,Q-i) = φ(Qi,Q-i). △
Lemma A.5 Let f be an Ergin-acyclic priority structure. Then, γ is non bossy.
Proof Follows from Ergin’s (2002) Theorem 1, (iv) ⇒ (iii) and proof of (iii) ⇒ (ii). ■
Lemma A.6 Let f be an Ergin-acyclic priority structure. Let 2 ≤ k ≤ m. Then, for any
school choice problem P all equilibrium outcomes in the game Γγ (P, k) are stable, i.e., for
all Q ∈ Eγ(P, k), γ(Q) ∈ S(P).
Proof Suppose to the contrary that Q ∈ Eγ(P, k) but γ(Q) ∈ S(P). So, by Lemma A.2,
there are i, j ∈ I, i = j and s ∈ S with γ(Q)(j) = s, sPiγ(Q)(i), and fs(i) < fs(j).
Since γ is strategy-proof in the unconstrained setting (i.e., when the quota equals m,
the number of schools), γ(Pi,Q-i)Riγ(Qi, Q-i). Let Qi := γ(Pi,Q-i)(i). Clearly, Qi ∈
Q(k). By Lemma A.1, γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) = γ(Pi,Q-i)(i). Hence, γ(Qi, Q-i)Riγ(Qi, Q-i).
If γ(Qi,Q-i)Piγ(Qi,Q-i), then Q ∈ Eγ(P, k), a contradiction. Hence, γ(Qi,Q-i)(i) =
γ(Qi,Q-i)(i).
By Lemma A.5, γ is non bossy. Hence, γ(Pi, Q-i) = γ(Qi, Q-i) = γ(Q). In particular,
γ(Pi, Q-i)(j) = γ(Q)(j) = s. Since sPiγ(Q)(i) = γ(Pi, Q-i)(i), student i has justified
envy at γ (Pi, Q-i), contradicting γ (Pi, Q-i) ∈ S (Pi, Q-i). Hence, γ(Q) ∈ S (P ). ■
Proof of Theorem 6.5 Proposition 6.1 implies that the game Γγ(P, 1) = Γβ(P, 1)
implements S(P) in Nash equilibria, i.e., S(P) = Oγ(P, 1). Theorem 5.3 implies that
S (P ) = Oγ (P, 1) ⊆ Oγ (P, k). Now Lemmas A.3 and A.6 complete the proof. ■
30
More intriguing information
1. Optimal Rent Extraction in Pre-Industrial England and France – Default Risk and Monitoring Costs2. The name is absent
3. Language discrimination by human newborns and by cotton-top tamarin monkeys
4. The name is absent
5. The name is absent
6. The name is absent
7. The Employment Impact of Differences in Dmand and Production
8. Nurses' retention and hospital characteristics in New South Wales, CHERE Discussion Paper No 52
9. Manufacturing Earnings and Cycles: New Evidence
10. If our brains were simple, we would be too simple to understand them.